{"id":515,"date":"2020-03-04T14:13:56","date_gmt":"2020-03-04T21:13:56","guid":{"rendered":"http:\/\/cjscf.org\/?page_id=515"},"modified":"2020-08-26T17:33:10","modified_gmt":"2020-08-26T23:33:10","slug":"essentialism-in-feminist-theology-identity-in-narrative-and-nature","status":"publish","type":"post","link":"https:\/\/cjscf.org\/theology\/essentialism-in-feminist-theology-identity-in-narrative-and-nature\/","title":{"rendered":"Essentialism in Feminist Theology: Identity in Narrative and Nature"},"content":{"rendered":"
\u00a0<\/strong><\/p>\n ESSENTIALISM IN FEMINIST THEOLOGY:\u00a0<\/strong>IDENTITY IN NARRATIVE AND NATURE<\/strong><\/p>\n <\/p>\n J. M. CALLAGHAN<\/p>\n <\/p>\n <\/p>\n Pr\u00e9cis<\/p>\n \u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0 Theologian Serene Jones, the first female president of Union Theological Seminary, has stated that, \u201cassumptions about what women are, and should be, are built into our theology and practices.\u201d[1]<\/sup><\/a> A brief survey of two-thousand years of church history and the works of its theologians, reveals a tradition replete with claims about the female nature.[2]<\/sup><\/a> The vast bulk of Christian literature during this time has preserved what most perceive as a subordinate view of women. Contrast this with the conviction of the complete equality of women with men, the staple of feminist thought and theology. What is less clear however is, to what degree (if any) there is a difference between the female and the male essence. Those who continue to embrace the notion that biological and non-biological differences between women and men are not just socially constructed but are somehow partially natural, generally fall under the umbrella category of \u201cessentialists.\u201d<\/p>\n As such, this paper will explore revised and newly framed formulations of essentialist theology which attempt to discard old, outdated and restrictive claims about the female essence, in favor of strategic or \u201cpragmatic essentialism,\u201d which provides a structure of narrative for a woman\u2019s identity.[3]<\/sup><\/a> For our purposes, this mode of essentialist speculation will be rooted in the Christian tradition and a synthesis of secular and theological thought. In this process we will examine some historical developments within feminist and gender theory that are relevant both to Christian theology and also for constructing a framework around the significance of \u201cfemaleness.\u201d All of this will be used in an attempt to explain why many women and men still choose to embrace \u201cuniversal\u201d claims about sexed nature, which undoubtedly provides a sense of foundational narrative for our individual and communal lives.[4]<\/sup><\/a><\/p>\n Introductory Remarks<\/p>\n Christian feminists have, over the past half-century, sought to bring their respective critiques and observations regarding society and culture into critical dialogue with the disciplines of theology and biblical studies.[5]<\/sup><\/a> In many respects, the general aims of secular and Christian feminists feature shared convictions about women\u2019s equality and the need to address oppressive practices and ideas in the world at large. The immense diversity within feminist thought, however, inevitably leads to differences. These differences are more apparent for feminists who remain committed to the historic, Christian faith, because their starting point is fundamentally distinct from secular feminists. Thus, there is always a dialectical push and pull between the two. This relationship is put well in the following, \u201cThere is not only a unity of concerns between feminist and Christian voices in this journey, but also a persistent and fruitful tension between them.\u201d[6]<\/sup><\/a> Elaine Storkey provides us with a more specific label, \u201cbiblical feminists,\u201d which describes those whose epistemological foundation begins with an acceptance of the Hebrew and Christian scriptures as somehow revelatory in nature and as \u201cauthentic communication from God.\u201d[7]<\/sup><\/a> Christian feminists who identify with some kind of biblical commitment are then, as a result, tasked with theologizing about what attention the bible gives to female existence and what it means to be a woman.<\/p>\n The Imago Dei <\/em>that humankind reflects is on its own a subject for philosophical pontification concerning the nature of humanity. The character of the Genesis creation account is such that it predisposes the Judeo-Christian tradition towards an adherence to a doctrine of creation.[8]<\/sup><\/a> What is particularly relevant is not just that humanity is formed in the image of God, but that humanity is composed of female and male individuals, who both represent God in some fashion. The following quote illuminates more precisely the ambiguity that essentialist theology might attempt to elucidate;<\/p>\n That<\/em> we are created male and female, and that<\/em> this difference plays a large part in the central human tasks of \u201creproduction, nurturing, survival,\u201d is indeed \u201cbeyond critical scrutiny.\u201d But what <\/em>that fixed point of reference signifies, is by no means beyond analysis.[9]<\/sup><\/a><\/p>\n<\/blockquote>\n \n Feminism, Essentialism & Historical Development<\/p>\n \u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0 As alluded to earlier, feminist thinkers have been hesitant to embrace \u201cdifference,\u201d as an appropriate term for the unique embodiment of men and women. Following the early women’s right\u2019s movements, the goal of early feminism was to establish the \u201cfoundational, non negotiable premise that women and men are equal.\u201d[10]<\/sup><\/a> This expanded beyond the suffrage movement to women\u2019s opportunities in the workplace and in society at large. During this pivotal time, many held that \u201cequal rights and opportunities could only be grounded in the presumption that women and men share the same nature.\u201d[11]<\/sup><\/a> For there was an understandable concern about the danger of over-emphasizing or conceding to the existence of differences between men and women. More specifically, a primary concern here, was that an affirmation of a \u201cnatural female essence…potentially reinstates and reinforces the very abuses feminism intends to fight.\u201d[12]<\/sup><\/a> In short, if one granted that women possessed an essential nature or a universal set of fixed characteristics, the inevitable result would be that fixed gender roles and attributes would be ascribed to all women, thus limiting the female experience. And even if one accepted the premise that there were differences between women and men, this emphasis on difference was altogether subjective, since one could just as easily make the case that the similarities between men and women far outweigh the differences.[13]<\/sup><\/a> Thus, many argued that any differences, whether actual or assumed, should be dismissed altogether so that women and men could interact as equals in daily life. But this solution was rejected by others. And so many began to argue that the answer to how the patriarchy \u201cdevalued\u201d womanhood was \u201cnot to deny but to appreciate those differences.\u201d[14]<\/sup><\/a> Some even began to argue that ignoring difference was just as much of an issue and was another method of erasing female existence. The point here being that, \u201cDifference and equality were never intended to be at opposite poles.\u201d[15]<\/sup><\/a><\/p>\n \u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0 And so this brings us to both a divergence among feminist thinkers, but also a middle ground for others, where a \u201cboth\/and\u201d perspective was embraced.[16]<\/sup><\/a> Over decades of feminist discourse, a number of theoretical impasses would emerge, highlighting some not insignificant ideological breaks. One of the first, was the sex-gender distinction made by gender theorists such as Simone de Beauvoir, which we will review shortly. The second and related juncture was the constructivist-essentialist divide. A third question, which like the previous two, remains unresolved for many, has been whether or not there is a single male-female nature or dual natures.[17]<\/sup><\/a> All three of these points of contention persist in academia today and are of course deeply interrelated. Before we outline the basic critiques of essentialism, we need to delineate what exactly these criticisms are directed towards and so we will quickly define older forms of essentialism.<\/p>\n Pre-modern and Biological Essentialism<\/p>\n \u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0 The basic thrust of essentialism is the, \u201cidea that a certain \u2018essence\u2019 defines the center of our identity as human beings and as men and women.\u201d[18]<\/sup><\/a> This has typically translated to some notion of \u201cfixed characteristics\u201d for both genders, which are natural.[19]<\/sup><\/a> Additionally, these fixed attributes have been considered to explain why gendered roles are and should be both descriptive and <\/em>prescriptive. This older or \u201cpre-modern\u201d essentialism is especially pertinent in a Christian context, because for most of history, and still for a great many Christians today, it has been viewed as normative for men and women. Typically, this involves defining womanhood and manhood with absolutized characteristics that are or should be true across cultural and societal lines.[20]<\/sup><\/a> Traditional forms of essentialist theology almost always translate to expectations within gender roles. Examples of this in Christian praxis might include; female exclusion from the clergy, male headship in marriage and general expectations about behavior, attire and sexuality.[21]<\/sup><\/a><\/p>\n \u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0 Additionally, we have \u201cbiological essentialism,\u201d which focuses on the natural differences (i.e. anatomical, physiological and hormonal etc.) between women and men and builds an essentialist paradigm in light of them.[22]<\/sup><\/a> For early feminists, this form of essentialism was still an acceptable fact of life. But as we will see next, many feminist thinkers would come to reject biological essentialism as well, due to its deterministic outlook.[23]<\/sup><\/a><\/p>\n The Constructivist Account: A Critique of Essentialist Claims<\/p>\n Even before many of the historical dynamics described above had taken place, gender theorists were beginning to question the parameters of gender as a category. One of the major innovations was the sex-gender distinction, which accepted that sex was biological, but stressed that gender was social.[24]<\/sup><\/a> Thus, one can see how the idea of gender being constructed rather than inherent, quickly emerged once this distinction was made. Because humans are unstable beings with inescapable mutability, change in personality always occurs over the course of one\u2019s life. Experiences and the environmental location in which we develop clearly play roles in shaping our identity. Therefore, in constructivism, \u201cthe body (sex) is raw material on which socially constructed mores (gender) inscribe themselves.\u201d[25]<\/sup><\/a><\/p>\n A number of pointed objections are then levied at essentialism and their validity should be well-taken. We\u2019ll list just a few. Essentialism posits a \u201cuniversal feminine,\u201d which tends to be either abstract and undefinable or contingent upon the gender norms of each particular time period.[26]<\/sup><\/a> Essentialism presupposes the existence of binary categories such as sex\/gender, male\/female and culture\/nature.[27]<\/sup><\/a> Likewise, feminists argue, due to concerns about a biologically based essentialism, that it \u201cmakes women\u2019s historical subordination to men seem like a natural fact rather than a cultural product.\u201d[28]<\/sup><\/a> While by no means exhaustively representative of the criticisms essentialism has been subjected to, these points do capture some of the primary observations which have undermined the legitimacy of essentialism as it pertains to human sex and gender. One further philosophical development must be addressed before we see how a recapitulated essentialism has escaped relegation to the intellectual basement.<\/p>\n The Postmodern Problem<\/p>\n \u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0 The complex and often vague philosophical term that is \u201cpostmodernism\u201d carries a host of meanings with it. The postmodern claims relevant to a discussion of essentialism have primarily to do with \u201cdeconstruction.\u201d Furthermore, for postmodern thinkers, \u201cthere are no essentials, no metanarratives, no overarching explanatory formulas.\u201d[29]<\/sup><\/a> The implications of these propositions should be self-evident, especially for Christians who take the metanarrative of scripture as a frame of reference for reality. The notion of deconstruction provides another conundrum for our conceptualization of sex\/gender, for postmodernists not only claim gender is constructed, but sex![30]<\/sup><\/a><\/p>\n Responding to Constructivism & Postmodernism: Strategic Essentialisms<\/p>\n Where does this dizzying array of critiques leave someone with essentialist inclinations? One has to wonder if essentialism is even viable anymore given its historical impedimenta. Certainly among scholastics, to speak of essential female or male natures or immanence (to borrow Beauvoir\u2019s language) or of a \u201cbasic feminine character structure,\u201d has become uncommon, but not unheard of among feminist theorists.[31]<\/sup><\/a> An inherent feminine nature is \u201cno longer orthodox,\u201d and for many gender theorists especially, it is a \u201crather heretical view.\u201d[32]<\/sup><\/a> But where there is heresy, there are also heretics and for many outside of the academic sphere, forms of essentialism are still embraced, unconsciously or consciously. While by far the minority within academia, a number of thinkers, both secular and religious, have postulated new approaches to essentialist paradigms.<\/p>\n The starting point for these voices is to acknowledge many of the criticisms aimed at pre-modern essentialism. There are a plethora of problems for an essentialist ideology or theology. At the same time there are some advantages, particularly from a Christian perspective. A starting point for a valuable essentialism takes place when it is a \u201crepresentative metaphor entailing human agency and practice, rather than a realist retreat into a nature against which human beings are powerless.\u201d[33]<\/sup><\/a> The worry about a kind of biological destiny is evident here. As such, too much emphasis on biology\u2019s role in gender identity should be taken into account as well as a realization that men and women share many similarities and thus it might be more helpful to focus on similarities rather than differences, depending on the context.[34]<\/sup><\/a> However, the counter-response to concerns about \u201cbiology as destiny\u201d[35]<\/sup><\/a> is a concern over a total denial of differences rooted in male-female bodies. And when it comes to theorizing about the natural differentiation between women and men, an essentialist \u201ctwo-nature\u201d theory does have some advantages as explained in the following;<\/p>\n Drawing from the account of creation in Genesis 2, the two-nature theory emphasizes the fact that men and women have very different bodies and reproductive tasks, but also more subtle differences. Men have more testosterone, women have more estrogen…The two-nature theory seems to explain some persistent patterns in human nature…The two nature-theory also takes account of the ways biological differences shape human lives.[36]<\/sup><\/a><\/p>\n<\/blockquote>\n \n The single nature theory does emphasize the unity of human<\/em> nature and reiterates that all faculties and abilities possessed by individuals are universal to women and men. At the same time, a shared human nature does not exhaust the unique \u201cdiversity\u201d of embodiment for women and men. Thus, it is important to place these theories of human and sexed nature in dialectical reciprocity.[37]<\/sup><\/a> But beyond biology and its role in the female identity, recovering or rethinking essentialism has come in a number of forms. For example, while most feminist essentialists would reject motherhood or \u201cmothering\u201d as a manifestation of essentialism since not every woman chooses to have children and some cannot biologically produce children, it is still a feature of life for the majority of women around the world both historically and presently. But to speak of motherhood is not to speak universally but rather in generality, for it is a staple of most women\u2019s lives. And to reject a very broad truth about existence simply because it is not true for every single individual is not helpful either. Take Wittgenstein\u2019s concept of \u201cfamily resemblance,\u201d where he noted that members from any given family can share some \u201cresemblance\u201d without necessarily bearing all<\/em> of the same qualities. In other words, general shared traits vs universal shared traits. Wittgenstein then applied this to words or conceptual categories, noting that the word \u201cgame\u201d can refer to many activities that are vastly different. Thus, with this in mind, the words or categories, \u201cmotherhood\u201d or \u201cmale\/female,\u201d can refer to broad characteristics shared within a certain category without universalizing particular aspects in a determinative manner.[38]<\/sup><\/a> Furthermore, even \u201cfor many radical feminists, the solution to such dichotomies lies not in women\u2019s rejecting <\/em>childbearing and child raising but rather in their regaining control <\/em>of both…By retrieving motherhood on their own terms…\u201d[39]<\/sup><\/a> This \u201cretrieval\u201d or reclamation of certain typically \u201cfeminine\u201d associated experiences is precisely that. However, while some feminists have encouraged women to embrace and take back certain female identities, they have rejected any claim that an identity of one woman is normative for the next and thus prefer to speak in generalities. This means that, while feminists might acknowledge women\u2019s unique experience as a nurturer, this does not exhaust or define the lives of all women, nor does it imply that men are any less capable of nurturing qualities. Thus as with feminist thinkers like Luce Irigaray, there is a call for the woman to free herself from the patriarchy and to \u201cbecome herself,\u201d while also embracing the beauty of difference between not just men and women but among all women too.[40]<\/sup><\/a> What emerges from this delicate balance is what has been coined as \u201cstrategic essentialism.\u201d[41]<\/sup><\/a><\/p>\n \u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0 While modern essentialists often end up in a very defensive posture, they have raised some critical points about the weaknesses of the constructivist account and postmodern philosophy. The most obvious response to social constructivism is that it makes us as humans mere byproducts of societal and environmental mores, which in some sense share deterministic parallels with biological destiny.[42]<\/sup><\/a> Additionally, essentialists protest that strong forms of constructivism can lead to relativistic outlooks where \u201cstandards\u201d by which to describe female suffering and injustice disappear into a larger paradigm that ultimately disadvantages women.[43]<\/sup><\/a> Seemingly, both accounts present faults. But, while postmodernity is critical of constructivist and essentialist language, it offers only less ground to stand on, making it increasingly difficult to create narratives about who we are as humans and as men and women. Furthermore, the postmodern deconstruction of both<\/em> sex and gender as categories contains a number of flaws. Postmodernists insightfully tell us that language (and thus the usage of terms like \u201cessentials,\u201d \u201csex\u201d and \u201cgender\u201d) has limitations alongside its inherent power. For, \u201clanguage constructs reality,\u201d and there is a profound \u201cinstability of all categories.\u201d[44]<\/sup><\/a> If this is the case, we then have to carefully reconsider and deconstruct how we\u2019ve delineated these categories, including those of sex and gender.[45]<\/sup><\/a> Because language is limited and is also used to accumulate power, there should be a hermeneutic of suspicion directed towards its usage. This postmodern critique makes important observations, but its own logic must be applied upon itself.[46]<\/sup><\/a> Furthermore, while there is of course a deep value to deconstruction, particularly regarding universal claims that have to do with our day to day existence, at some point we need to construct meaning for our lives and our self-perception. Ultimately, the rejection of any kind of metanarrative, of even an abstract notion of the \u201cuniversal feminine,\u201d which for many people carries a great deal of significance, is what makes the postmodern deconstruction of sex and gender unhelpful for many. This is why, despite remarkable limitations, a theological narrative around the nature of sex\/gender matters. Similarly, despite legitimate concerns about exaggerations promulgated by biological essentialism, postmodern deconstruction ultimately founders on the rock of biological reality. Consider the unique health challenges that men and women face, where for example, females but not males are at risk for cervical cancer. This is not a socially constructed reality and can be rooted in normative biological categories.<\/p>\n The Importance of Narrative and Nature<\/p>\n \u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0 Elaine Storkey gives us four <\/em>paradigms from which to understand the biblical depiction of female-male existence, uniqueness and relations; difference<\/em>, sameness\/similarity<\/em>, complementarity<\/em> and union<\/em>.[47]<\/sup><\/a> Each of these themes represents separate but interrelated aspects of our \u201cessentialized\u201d createdness in the image of God. Storkey highlights the connection between sameness and difference in the following:<\/p>\n As Christians, we understand that both men and women are created in God\u2019s image, and that both are the subjects of redemption history. Thus men and women are fundamentally equal. Yet the Creator, whose appreciation of diversity vibrates throughout creation, made both men and women as human beings embodied differently and thus bound to experience the creation in certain unique ways. Accordingly, equality and diversity are at the heart of creation, and at the center of the human community.[48]<\/sup><\/a><\/p>\n \n There is then a complementarity implied in the differences, at least biologically, in that reproduction requires specific contributions from each sex. And finally the differences and complementarity make the concept of \u201cunion\u201d possible, given that union, as opposed to uniformity, requires differences coming together in a complementary manner.<\/p>\n Thus, we can see how the Genesis narrative captures all four of these paradigms. Creation begins with sameness before differentiation takes place. But shortly after, the complementary nature of reproduction and mutual partnership leads to unity. The concept of union necessitates a difference and what brings the differences together is the complementarity (not in the hierarchical sense).<\/p>\n \u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0 Many commentators have noted that in the Genesis creation account, humanity is only seen as wholly complete when both<\/em> male and female are present.[49]<\/sup><\/a> A dismissal or misuse of the Genesis account loses sight of its theological and existential weight. For regardless of debates about historicity or interpretation, the story of Eve and Adam is the beginning of the Christian tradition and it carries with it the authoritative gravity of God\u2019s creative designs for humanity. This means that while individuals will always form their own essentialist (or constructivist) identities, we must also define ourselves on a larger scale;<\/p>\n Individualistic solutions…cannot unravel the complexities of gender, for in the end gender is not about individual men and women but about the differences that emerge when men and women are in relationship<\/em> in human communities. To understand and attempt to connect the injustice of gender relations, we must explore the dynamics of men and women in relationship with each other.[50]<\/sup><\/a><\/p>\n \n Conclusion<\/p>\n \u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0\u00a0 A theologically essentialist paradigm is grounded in the narrative of scripture with the diversity of humanity showcased in the added diversity among all women and all men. The distinctive features between the sexes and among the both sex groups are reasons to uphold and celebrate the ways in which attributes found in both men and women reflect God. Similarly, we can honor and recognize that, \u201cMale and female are sexual categories and we experience much of our identity through our sexuality.\u201d[51]<\/sup><\/a> An essentialist may contend, with many qualifications, that, \u201cthe female body carries meaning in and of itself, which is the ground for women\u2019s identity and also potentially for women\u2019s solidarity as a group.\u201d[52]<\/sup><\/a> Essentialism based on narrative and collective identity, moves beyond individualistic and subjective ways of identifying, allowing women and men to enter into a larger story. This narrative, speaks of the radical equality, difference, similarity and createdness of human beings and highlights that we are more than mere byproducts of stardust, but also more than just our surroundings. To humbly embrace the distinctiveness endowed upon us by our Creator provides a foundation to build a purposeful life. And lastly it reminds us that;<\/p>\n Sustaining a dynamic dialogue between Christianity and feminism occurs when unique and distinct voices are not collapsed into one another. Preserving distinction when appropriate allows us to walk alongside those with whom we disagree, and it is this type of relation that the possibility of hearing a corrective voice or new word occurs. Often this means allowing the light of truth in feminist theory to perform the demanding work of chipping away at patriarchal traditions Christianity often inherits and generates. Equally important, it implies continually asking what light the revelation of God\u2019s self in scripture, tradition and experience may bring to feminist theory.[53]<\/sup><\/a><\/p>\n<\/blockquote>\n \n \n Bibliography<\/p>\n DallaValle, Nancy A. \u201cNeither Idolatry Nor Iconoclasm: A Critical Essentialism for Catholic Feminist Theology.\u201d Horizons <\/em>25, no 1 (Spring 1998): 23-42.<\/p>\n <\/p>\n Japinga, Lynn. Feminism and Christianity: An Essential Guide. <\/em>Nashville, TN: Abingdon Press, 1999.<\/p>\n <\/p>\n Jones, Serene. Feminist Theory and Christian Theology: Cartographies of Grace<\/em>. Minneapolis, MN: Fortress Press, 2000.<\/p>\n <\/p>\n Knoppers, Annelies, Margaret L. Koch, Douglas J. Schuurman and Helen M. Sterk. After Eden:\u00a0<\/em>Facing the Challenge of Gender Reconciliation<\/em> edited by Mary Stewart Van Leeuwen. Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 1993.<\/p>\n <\/p>\n Leclerc, Diane. \u201cTwo Women Speaking \u201cWoman\u201d: The Strategic Essentialism of Luce Irigaray and Phoebe Palmer.\u201d In Being Feminist, Being Christian: Essays from Academia <\/em>edited\u00a0by Allyson Jule and Bettina Tate Pedersen, (New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan, 2006):\u00a0111-126.<\/p>\n <\/p>\n Lindley, Susan Hill. \u201cYou Have Stept Out of Your Place.\u201d A History of Women and Religion in\u00a0America. Louisville, KY: Westminster John Knox Press, 1996.<\/p>\n <\/p>\n Maeckelberghe, Els. \u201cAcross the Generations in Feminist Theology: From Second to Third\u00a0Wave Feminisms.\u201d Feminist Theology<\/em> 23, (January 2000): 63-69.<\/p>\n <\/p>\n Powell, Elizabeth. \u201cIn Search of Bodily Perspective: A Study of Simone de Beauvoir and Luce Irigaray.\u201d In Being Feminist, Being Christian: Essays from Academia <\/em>edited by Allyson Jule and Bettina Tate Pedersen, (New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan, 2006): 81-109.<\/p>\n <\/p>\n Storkey, Elaine. Origins of Difference: The Gender Debate Revisited<\/em>. Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Academic, 2001.<\/p>\n <\/p>\n Wittgenstein, Ludwig. Philosophische Untersuchungen<\/em>. Revised Fourth Edition. Translated by\u00a0G.E.M. Anscombe, P.M.S. Hacker and Joachim Schulte. West Sussex, UK: Blackwell Publishing, 2009.<\/p>\n <\/p>\n <\/p>\n <\/p>\n [1]<\/sup><\/a> Serene Jones, Feminist Theory and Christian Theology: Cartographies of Grace<\/em>, (Minneapolis, MN: Fortress Press, 2000), 23.<\/p>\n [2]<\/sup><\/a> French philosopher and feminist theorist Simone de Beauvoir made note of how women\u2019s nature has been described both as inferior and as deficient. Beauvoir draws attention to the commentary on women found in Aristotelian literature and that of the great scholastic theologian, St. Thomas Aquinas as just two examples of deeply embedded negative perceptions about the \u201cdifferent,\u201d and \u201clesser\u201d nature of the female sex. St. Aquinas asserted that the woman was both an \u201cimperfect man,\u201d and an \u201cincidental person.\u201d See Simone de Beauvoir, The Second Sex <\/em>translated by Judith Thurman, (New York, NY: Vintage Books, 2011), 5.<\/p>\n [3]<\/sup><\/a> Serene Jones, Feminist Theory and Christian Theology: Cartographies of Grace<\/em>, 44.<\/p>\n [4]<\/sup><\/a> By narrative, we mean, \u201cstory,\u201d in which a certain paradigm or worldview provides us with both a map to navigate the world and concepts in which to relate to and build our personal and collective identities off of. For helpful works that delve into how story, narrative and mythology relate to reality and human consciousness see Stephen D. Crites, \u201cThe Narrative Quality of Experience,\u201d Journal of the American Academy of Religion<\/em> 39, no. 3 (September 1971): 291-311.<\/p>\n [5]<\/sup><\/a> Feminist theology (which shouldn\u2019t be interpreted as a uniform ideology with a singular set of systematic principles) as a modern school of thought or philosophy gained momentum following the work of Valerie Saiving and an article authored by her in 1960. See Valerie Saiving, \u201cThe Human Situation: A Feminine View,\u201d Journal of Feminist Studies in Religion<\/em> 28, no.1 (1960): 75-78. Subsequent early major Christian <\/em>feminist thinkers in the 1960\u2019s and afterwards included; Mary Daly, Rosemary Radford Ruether, Elizabeth Sch\u00fcssler Fiorenza and Phyllis Trible. Feminist critiques of religion and Christianity also appeared in the 19th century and can be found within the works of Elizabeth Cady Stanton, Margaret Fuller and Matilda Joslyn Gage. See Susan Hill. Lindley, \u201cYou Have Stept Out of Your Place.\u201d A History of Women and Religion in America<\/em>, (Louisville, KY: Westminster John Knox Press, 1996), 275-297. Feminist responses to the Christian faith and its relation to women varied in both the 19th and 20th centuries. For an introduction to some of the basic concerns and issues raised by feminist theologians see Regina M. Bechtle, \u201cFeminist Approaches to Theology,\u201d The Way<\/em> 27, no. 1 (April 1987): 124-131.<\/p>\n [6]<\/sup><\/a> Elizabeth Powell, \u201cIn Search of Bodily Perspective: A Study of Simone de Beauvoir and Luce Irigaray.\u201d In Being Feminist, Being Christian: Essays from Academia <\/em>edited by Allyson Jule and Bettina Tate Pedersen, (New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan, 2006): 103.<\/p>\n [7]<\/sup><\/a> Elaine Storkey, Origins of Difference: The Gender Debate Revisited<\/em>, (Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Academic, 2001), 111-112. Storkey explains how the starting point of biblical femininsts functions distinctly from the primary feminist hermeneutic of experience in the following insightful comment; \u201c…biblical feminists are at odds epistemologically with much of the rest of feminist theology, for they reject the primacy of women\u2019s experience as the interpretive framework with which to approach the Bible. For them, although experience is crucially important, it cannot be the standpoint from which we understand reality. As authentic communication from God, the biblical text cannot simply be subject to women\u2019s experience as some \u201chigher order\u201d that ultimately arbitrates over it. Women\u2019s experience cannot have the last word, for experience itself has to be examined and understood. There has to be an intricate two-way relationship of experience and revelation, in which experience is seen in relation to God. Since the basis of human identity is given, created by God, not simply constructed out of the particulars of our world, we have to be prepared to allow the depths of God\u2019s revelation to interpret us as we seek to understand our worth and calling before God.\u201d (112).<\/p>\n [8]<\/sup><\/a> And because Christians uphold God as creator, there is already an element of \u201ccreation\/nature\u201d imbued into humanity and one could argue an essentialism in the Imago Dei <\/em>that each individual inherently possesses. Elaine Storkey reiterates the relevance of this point to the creation-construction debate, \u201cIf we are brought into being by a Creator, and thereby dependent on that Creator for our existence, we have already come down on one side of the creation-construction debate. Yet, we can still hold that our sexuality is put into creation by God and recognize that our differences\u00a0 might also be developmental and cultural. See Elaine Storkey, Origins of Difference: The Gender Debate Revisited<\/em>, 97-98.<\/p>\n [9]<\/sup><\/a> Nancy A. Dallavalle, \u201cNeither Idolatry nor Iconoclasm: A Critical Essentialism for Catholic Feminist Theology,\u201d Horizons <\/em>25, no.1 (Spring 1998): 32. Here Dallavalle is quoting theologian and gender theorist Eileen Graham. See Eileen Graham, \u201cGender, Personhood and Theology,\u201d Scottish Journal of Theology <\/em>48, (1995): 341-358.<\/p>\n [10]<\/sup><\/a> Susan Hill. Lindley, \u201cYou Have Stept Out of Your Place.\u201d A History of Women and Religion in America<\/em>, 426.<\/p>\n [11]<\/sup><\/a> Ibid.<\/p>\n [12]<\/sup><\/a> Diane Leclerc, \u201cTwo Women Speaking \u201cWoman\u201d: The Strategic Essentialism of Luce Irigaray and Phoebe Palmer,\u201d In Being Feminist, Being Christian: Essays from Academia <\/em>edited by Allyson Jule and Bettina Tate Pedersen, (New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan, 2006): 112.<\/p>\n [13]<\/sup><\/a> \u201cFar from being an expression of natural differences, exclusive gender identity is the suppression of natural similarities.\u201d See Gayle Rubin, \u201cThe Traffic in Women: Notes on the \u2018Political Economy\u2019 of Sex,\u201d in Toward an Anthropology of Women<\/em> edited by R.R. Reitr (New York, NY: Monthly Review Press, 1975), 179-180.<\/p>\n [14]<\/sup><\/a> Lindley, \u201cYou Have Stept Out of Your Place.\u201d A History of Women and Religion in America<\/em>, 426.<\/p>\n [15]<\/sup><\/a> Margaret Koch, \u201cA Cross-Cultural Critique of Western Feminism,\u201d in After Eden: Facing the Challenge of Gender Reconciliation<\/em> edited by Mary Stewart Van Leeuwen, (Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 1993), 104.<\/p>\n [16]<\/sup><\/a> Lindley, \u201cYou Have Stept Out of Your Place.\u201d A History of Women and Religion in America<\/em>, 426.<\/p>\n [17]<\/sup><\/a> Generally speaking, \u201cTwo explanations for the similarities and differences of men and women have emerged in psychological and religious literature. The first emphasizes the differences and claims that men and women actually have two different natures. The second emphasizes the similarities, arguing that men and women share the same nature and differ only in the biological structure and capacity of their bodies.\u201d See Lynn Japinga, Feminism and Christianity: An Essential Guide<\/em>, (Nashville, TN: Abingdon Press, 1999), 81.<\/p>\n\n
\n
\n